Skip to main content
Log in

Defining features versus incidental correlates of Type 1 and Type 2 processing

  • Published:
Mind & Society Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Many critics of dual-process models have mistaken long lists of descriptive terms in the literature for a full-blown theory of necessarily co-occurring properties. These critiques have distracted attention from the cumulative progress being made in identifying the much smaller set of properties that truly do define Type 1 and Type 2 processing. Our view of the literature is that autonomous processing is the defining feature of Type 1 processing. Even more convincing is the converging evidence that the key feature of Type 2 processing is the ability to sustain the decoupling of secondary representations. The latter is a foundational cognitive requirement for hypothetical thinking.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Keren and Schul (2009) use the fractionation of the automaticity concept that we discussed previously as a negative example: “Bargh (1994) noted, almost 15 years ago, that automaticity may not be a single concept in the sense that manifestations of automaticity (such as non-awareness, non-intentionality, efficiency, and non-controllability) are not aligned” (p. 539). But as we noted above, years before Bargh (1994), Stanovich (1990) argued the same thing. However, contrary to Keren and Schul’s implication, the fractionation of the concept into its essential features versus its incidental correlates helped rather than hurt the reading field. The latter field still profits from the distinction between Type 1 and Type 2 processing.

  2. Keren and Schul (2009) have fun with other caricatures: “We are [concerned]…with the very strong claim that a limited set of binary attributes can be combined in only one, single, unique way, permitting the existence of exactly two systems (and no more!)” (p. 538). The “no more” is funny, but nonetheless a straw man since that has never been an assumption of dual-process theory, as Gilbert (1999) noted over a decade ago: “Few of the psychologists whose chapters appear in this volume would claim that the dual processes in their models necessarily correspond to the activity of two distinct brain structures…. Psychologists who champion dual-process models are not usually stuck on two. Few would come undone if their models were recast in terms of three processes, or four, or even five. Indeed, the only number they would not happily accept is one, because claims about dual processes in psychology are not so much claims about how many processes there are, but claims about how many processes there aren’t. And the claim is this: There aren’t one” (pp. 3–4).

References

  • Aron AR (2008) Progress in executive-function research: from tasks to functions to regions to networks. Curr Dir Psychol Sci 17:124–129

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bargh JA (1994) The four horsemen of automaticity: awareness, intention, efficiency, and control in social cognition. In: Wyer RS Jr, Srull TK (eds) Handbook of social cognition, 2nd edn. Erlbaum, New Jersey, pp 1–40

    Google Scholar 

  • Barrett HC, Kurzban R (2006) Modularity in cognition: framing the debate. Psychol Rev 113:628–647

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Best JR, Miller PH, Jones LL (2009) Executive functions after age 5: changes and correlates. Dev Rev 29:180–200

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers P (2006) The architecture of the mind. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Conway ARA, Cowan N, Bunting MF, Therriault DJ, Minkoff SRB (2002) A latent variable analysis of working memory capacity, short-term memory capacity, processing speed, and general fluid intelligence. Intelligence 30:163–183

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cosmides L (1989) The logic of social exchange: has natural selection shaped how humans reason? Studies with the Wason selection task. Cognition 31:187–276

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coyle TR (2003) A review of the worst performance rule: evidence, theory, and alternative hypotheses. Intelligence 31:567–587

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dawes RM (1976) Shallow psychology. In: Carroll JS, Payne JW (eds) Cognition and social behavior. Erlbaum, Hillsdale, pp 3–11

    Google Scholar 

  • Deary IJ (2000) Looking down on human intelligence: from psychometrics to the brain. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett DC (1984) Elbow room: the varieties of free will worth wanting. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Dienes Z, Perner J (1999) A theory of implicit and explicit knowledge. Behav Brain Sci 22:735–808

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Engle RW (2002) Working memory capacity as executive attention. Curr Dir Psychol Sci 11:19–23

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans JStBT (2007) Hypothetical thinking: dual processes in reasoning and judgment. Psychology Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans JStBT (2008) Dual-processing accounts of reasoning, judgment and social cognition. Annu Rev Psychol 59:255–278

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans JStBT (2009) How many dual-process theories do we need? One, two, or many? In: Evans J, Frankish K (eds) In two minds: dual processes and beyond. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 33–54

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Evans JStBT (2010) Thinking twice: two minds in one brain. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans JStBT, Frankish K (2009) In two minds: dual processes and beyond. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Evans JStBT, Over DE (1999) Explicit representations in hypothetical thinking. Behav Brain Sci 22:763–764

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans JStBT, Over DE (2004) If. Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Evans JStBT, Over DE, Handley SJ (2003) A theory of hypothetical thinking. In: Hardman D, Maachi L (eds) Thinking: psychological perspectives on reasoning. Wiley, Chicester, pp 3–22

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor JA (1983) The modularity of mind. MIT University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert DT (1999) What the mind’s not. In: Chaiken S, Trope Y (eds) Dual-process theories in social psychology. Guilford Press, New York, pp 3–11

    Google Scholar 

  • Hasher L, Lustig C, Zacks R (2007) Inhibitory mechanisms and the control of attention. In: Conway A, Jarrold C, Kane M, Miyake A, Towse J (eds) Variation in working memory. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 227–249

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn JL, Cattell RB (1967) Age differences in fluid and crystallized intelligence. Acta Psychol 26:1–23

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jaeggi SM, Buschkuehl M, Jonides J, Perrig WJ (2008) Improved fluid intelligence with training in working memory. P Natl A Sci USA 105:6829–6833

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman D (2003) A perspective on judgment and choice: mapping bounded rationality. Am Psychol 58:697–720

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman D, Frederick S (2002) Representativeness revisited: attribute substitution in intuitive judgment. In: Gilovich T, Griffin D, Kahneman D (eds) Heuristics and biases: the psychology of intuitive judgment. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp 49–81

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman D, Klein G (2009) Conditions for intuitive expertise: a failure to disagree. Am Psychol 64:515–526

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kane MJ, Engle RW (2002) The role of prefrontal cortex working-memory capacity, executive attention, and general fluid intelligence: an individual-differences perspective. Psychon B Rev 9:637–671

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keren G, Schul Y (2009) Two is not always better than one: a critical evaluation of two-system theories. Perspect Psychol Sci 4:533–550

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kruglanski A, Gigerenzer G (2011) Intuitive and deliberate judgments are based on common principles. Psychol Rev 118:97–109

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • LaBerge D, Samuels S (1974) Toward a theory of automatic information processing in reading. Cognitive Psychol 6:293–323

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lepine R, Barrouillet P, Camos V (2005) What makes working memory spans so predictive of high-level cognition? Psychon B Rev 12:165–170

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leslie AM (1987) Pretense and representation: the origins of “theory of mind”. Psychol Rev 94:412–426

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lieberman MD (2003) Reflexive and reflective judgment processes: a social cognitive neuroscience approach. In: Forgas JP, Williams KR, von Hippel W (eds) Social judgments: implicit and explicit processes. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp 44–67

    Google Scholar 

  • Lieberman MD (2007) Social cognitive neuroscience: areview of core processes. Annu Rev Psychol 58:259–289

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marcovitch S, Boseovski JJ, Knapp RJ, Kane MJ (2010) Goal neglect and working memory capacity in 4- to 6-year-old children. Child Dev 81:1687–1695

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newstead SE (2000) Are there two different types of thinking? Behav Brain Sci 23:690–691

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols S, Stich SP (2003) Mindreading: an integrated account of pretence, self-awareness, and understanding other minds. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Osman M (2004) An evaluation of dual-process theories of reasoning. Psychon B Rev 11:988–1010

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perner J (1991) Understanding the representational mind. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Posner MI, Snyder CRR (1975) Attention and cognitive control. In: Solso RL (ed) Information processing and cognition: the Loyola symposium. Wiley, New York, pp 55–85

    Google Scholar 

  • Salthouse TA, Pink JE (2008) Why is working memory related to fluid intelligence? Psychon B Rev 15:364–371

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuels R (2005) The complexity of cognition: tractability arguments for massive modularity. In: Carruthers P, Laurence S, Stich S (eds) The innate mind. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 107–121

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Samuels R (2009) The magical number two, plus or minus: dual-process theory as a theory of cognitive kinds. In: Evans JStBT, Frankish K (eds) In two minds: dual processes and beyond. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 129–146

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Shiffrin RM, Schneider W (1977) Controlled and automatic human information processing: II perceptual learning, automatic attending, and a general theory. Psychol Rev 84:127–190

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slovic P, Peters E (2006) Risk perception and affect. Curr Dir Psychol Sci 15:322–325

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sperber D (1994) The modularity of thought and the epidemiology of representations. In: Hirschfeld LA, Gelman SA (eds) Mapping the mind: domain specificity in cognition and culture. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 39–67

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sperber D (2000) Metarepresentations in evolutionary perspective. In: Sperber D (ed) Metarepresentations: a multidisciplinary perspective. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 117–137

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanovich KE (1990) Concepts in developmental theories of reading skill: cognitive resources, automaticity, and modularity. Dev Rev 10:72–100

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanovich KE (1999) Who is rational? Studies of individual differences in reasoning. Erlbaum, Mahwah

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanovich KE (2004) The robot’s rebellion: finding meaning in the age of Darwin. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanovich KE (2009) Distinguishing the reflective, algorithmic, and autonomous minds: is it time for a tri-process theory? In: Evans JStBT, Frankish K (eds) In two minds: dual processes and beyond. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 55–88

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Stanovich KE (2011) Rationality and the reflective mind. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K (2003) Thought in a hostile world: the evolution of human cognition. Blackwell Publishing, Malden

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor SE (1981) The interface of cognitive and social psychology. In: Harvey JH (ed) Cognition, social behavior, and the environment. Erlbaum, Hillsdale, pp 189–211

    Google Scholar 

  • Tversky A, Kahneman D (1974) Judgment under uncertainty: heuristics and biases. Science 185:1124–1131

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wang L (2009) Money and fame: vividness effects in the National Basketball Association. J Behav Decis Making 22:20–44

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • West RF, Stanovich KE (1978) Automatic contextual facilitation in readers of three ages. Child Dev 49:717–727

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zbrodoff NJ, Logan GD (1986) On the autonomy of mental processes: a case study of arithmetic. J Exp Psychol Gen 115:118–130

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zelazo PD (2004) The development of conscious control in childhood. Trends Cogn Sci 8:12–17

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Keith E. Stanovich.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Stanovich, K.E., Toplak, M.E. Defining features versus incidental correlates of Type 1 and Type 2 processing. Mind Soc 11, 3–13 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11299-011-0093-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11299-011-0093-6

Keywords

Navigation